Table of Contents
- 1 Are all computable functions primitive recursive?
- 2 Are all computable functions recursive?
- 3 Are all functions computable?
- 4 Who said all functions algorithms which are intuitively computable are also Turing machine computable?
- 5 Where is Ackermann function used?
- 6 Are all problems computable?
- 7 How do you prove that a recursive function is computable?
- 8 What are the proofs of recursion?
Are all computable functions primitive recursive?
The importance of primitive recursive functions lies on the fact that most computable functions that are studied in number theory (and more generally in mathematics) are primitive recursive. The set of primitive recursive functions is known as PR in computational complexity theory.
Are all computable functions recursive?
In computability theory, computable functions are also called recursive functions. At least at first sight, they do not have anything in common with what you call “recursive” in day-to-day programming (i.e., functions that call themselfes).
Which among the following is not an example of primitive recursive function?
Discussion Forum
Que. | Which of the following is not a primitive recursive but partially recursive? |
---|---|
b. | Ricmaan function |
c. | Both (a) and (b) |
d. | Ackermann’s function |
Answer:Ackermann’s function |
Is Ackermann function primitive recursive?
“Ackermann function is not primitive recursive | planetmath.org”.
Are all functions computable?
Every such function is computable. It is not known whether there are arbitrarily long runs of fives in the decimal expansion of π, so we don’t know which of those functions is f. Nevertheless, we know that the function f must be computable.)
Who said all functions algorithms which are intuitively computable are also Turing machine computable?
In 1930, this statement was first formulated by Alonzo Church and is usually referred to as Church’s thesis, or the Church-Turing thesis. However, this hypothesis cannot be proved. The recursive functions can be computable after taking following assumptions: Each and every function must be computable.
Which of the following is NOT example of recursion?
Which of the following is not an example of recursion? Explanation: SFS is not an example of recursion.
Is Ackermann function computable?
The Ackermann function is the simplest example of a well-defined total function which is computable but not primitive recursive, providing a counterexample to the belief in the early 1900s that every computable function was also primitive recursive (Dötzel 1991).
Where is Ackermann function used?
The original “use” of the Ackermann function was to show that there are functions which are not primitive recursive, i.e. which cannot be computed by using only for loops with predetermined upper limits. The Ackermann function is such a function, it grows too fast to be primitive recursive.
Are all problems computable?
A mathematical problem is computable if it can be solved in principle by a computing device. Some common synonyms for “computable” are “solvable”, “decidable”, and “recursive”. Hilbert believed that all mathematical problems were solvable, but in the 1930’s Gödel, Turing, and Church showed that this is not the case.
What does it mean to be effectively computable?
is effectively computable if there is an effective procedure or algorithm that correctly calculates f. An effective procedure is one that meets the following specifications.
When a recursive function is called in the absence?
Explanation: When a recursive function is called in the absence of an exit condition, it results in an infinite loop due to which the stack keeps getting filled(stack overflow). This results in a run time error.
How do you prove that a recursive function is computable?
You prove it by structural induction over the definition of primitive recursive functions. The definition of computable is: a function is computable if it is computable by a Turing machine. There are many other equivalent definitions.
What are the proofs of recursion?
E.g. for any terminating Turing machine there exists a µ recursive function which calculates the same result. For any µ recursive function there exists a terminating Turing machine which calculates the same result. These proofs can be found in recursion theory. The proofs are general.
What is a computable function?
In computability theory, computable functions are also called recursive functions. At least at first sight, they do not have anything in common with what you call “recursive” in day-to-day programming (i.e., functions that call themselfes).
Why do we need register machines?
Thus by using register machines, we arrive at exactly the class of general recursive partial functions, a class we originally defined in terms of primitive recursion and search. EABI dictates the way the machine registers are applied by a compiler. Three categories of register are defined: